...
Show More
I stumbled upon this book at a very opportune moment in my life. In my drive towards understanding the nature of reality I had been recently engrossed in certain problems of a philosophical nature that had to do with the inadequacy of the metaphysical presuppositions of the scientific worldview in doing justice to the phenomenon of life and mind. I always suspected that our scientific models would gain much if the current scientific paradigm engaged in a critical re examination of its own foundations. This would not only help it reframe the phenomenon of life in terms more suited to its own concrete factuality but also help circumscribe the domain of applicability of principles like reductionism, extrinsic causality, the persistence of identity in the notion of substance and wholes taken as being no more than sums of their parts, all notions which, while being demonstrably effective in the analysis of non-living nature as such, inevitably hit against the outer limit of their pragmatic usefulness when confronted with the phenomenon of life. I approached this book keeping in view three primary problems which directly pertained to these lines of thought, namely:
1. The Mind-Body Problem and it's contemporary reframing as The Hard Problem of Consciousness
2. The nature of causality in light of the devastating critique of Hume and the insufficiency of Kant's transcendental solution.
3. The inadequacy of mechanistic models in Biology and the machine metaphor in general.
This book not only contains a highly original discussion of the aforementioned problems but also brought to light certain connections between them that I had only vaguely perceived beforehand. It went on to reveal their inner unity in the same prevalent but deficient worldview which came about as a result of misfired attempts to understand the nature of being qua being and the ontological priority of death over life that reigns in our current historical epoch in the form of materialistic monism. The book helped me understand the necessity for Whitehead to posit the role of 'causal efficacy' in contrast to 'presentational immediacy' as the more original and prior mode of perception that fades out of view in the dominant mode of perception, e.g vision in which the object presents itself to a passive subject in a form entirely divorced from its causal nexus. This causal nexus can be directly felt in the proprioceptive feelings of the living body, whose significance was entirely missed by Hume and whose wider application to nature at large is unthinkable for science as it stands now as it would be an instance of the sin of anthropomorphism. The book highlights the nature of the practise of science as pushing anti-anthropomorphism to its ultimate limit in which man and the scientific observer himself comes to be viewed from this perspective thereby nullifying the validity of his own reasoning as a thinking subject by a performative contradiction in a form of reductio ad absurdum.
Another feature of the book is it's exemplification of these philosophical problems not as isolated conceptual curiosities but as moments in a historical process that reminds one of Hegel's dialectics. Instead of the naive view of science progressing by a gradual accumulation of its qualities in a linear fashion, the complex reality of an oscillatory movement in which knowledge struggles to articulate the nature of being via a process close to:
A. Discovering a tention within a pre existing monism with attempts at concealment in order to preserve the original unity.
B. The tention erupting into a polarity which can no longer be suppressed. Attempts to eliminate the polarity by a reduction of one side to the other.
C. A dualism in which the polarity is acknowledged but cleanly separated into two parallel domains.
D. A synthesis that respects the original tention and yet results into a higher unity.
Hans Jonas explains how the various attempts at understanding the nature of being, despite being seemingly contingent products of prolific geniuses at critical junctures in history, still can be viewed as moments of a grand historical dialectic, thus revealing the imminent necessity of their contingent eruption in time.
The rigour and depth of the book in the treatment of its subject matter is matched only in its broad scope that ranges from discussions of the aforementioned problems to a treatment of gnosticism and it's relation with contemporary nihilism and existentialism. This is fitting for a book that re examines the nature of being and man not in terms of the tyranny of abstraction but in the concrete corporeality of man qua man. It affirms the intuition that an analysis of man can only be adequate if it gives voice to his being-in-the-world instead of falling prey to a deficient abstract system that suffers from Whitehead's fallacy of misplaced concreteness.
That being said I disagree with Jonas's contentions with Whitehead's philosophical scheme. Michael Levin's work has shown that postulating the properties of life as universal to 'being' as such with the difference being of degree rather than kind is a valid postulate that is not in conflict with empirical findings, assuming that you take the principle of least action in physics as an exemplar of its minimal yet fundamental incidence in nature.
Finally, by analysing the psychological undercurrents that held sway in the era in which gnosticism sprung up in history, Jonas digs deep underneath the surface mythology of the gnostics and reveals how it sprang from their worldview of alienation from the cosmos. Something being repeated in the modern era after the loss of the horizon of transcendence that was lamented by Nietzsche. It shows how the improper relations of part to whole in which there is a tyrannical supremacy of one side over the other gives way to an ontology of power in which domination can be overcome either by passive resignation to fate as in spinozism / stoicism or rebellious yet frightened self assertion as in existentialism, Heideggerian being-towards-death or gnosticism.
Reading this book was nothing short of an intellectual tour de force. As everything began to fall into place I experienced what can only be described like an aesthetic experience of consummated rational contemplation. To fully appreciate the subtle points of the arguments of this book one should be familiar with basic philosophy but I would recommend it highly to anyone sufficiently curious.
1. The Mind-Body Problem and it's contemporary reframing as The Hard Problem of Consciousness
2. The nature of causality in light of the devastating critique of Hume and the insufficiency of Kant's transcendental solution.
3. The inadequacy of mechanistic models in Biology and the machine metaphor in general.
This book not only contains a highly original discussion of the aforementioned problems but also brought to light certain connections between them that I had only vaguely perceived beforehand. It went on to reveal their inner unity in the same prevalent but deficient worldview which came about as a result of misfired attempts to understand the nature of being qua being and the ontological priority of death over life that reigns in our current historical epoch in the form of materialistic monism. The book helped me understand the necessity for Whitehead to posit the role of 'causal efficacy' in contrast to 'presentational immediacy' as the more original and prior mode of perception that fades out of view in the dominant mode of perception, e.g vision in which the object presents itself to a passive subject in a form entirely divorced from its causal nexus. This causal nexus can be directly felt in the proprioceptive feelings of the living body, whose significance was entirely missed by Hume and whose wider application to nature at large is unthinkable for science as it stands now as it would be an instance of the sin of anthropomorphism. The book highlights the nature of the practise of science as pushing anti-anthropomorphism to its ultimate limit in which man and the scientific observer himself comes to be viewed from this perspective thereby nullifying the validity of his own reasoning as a thinking subject by a performative contradiction in a form of reductio ad absurdum.
Another feature of the book is it's exemplification of these philosophical problems not as isolated conceptual curiosities but as moments in a historical process that reminds one of Hegel's dialectics. Instead of the naive view of science progressing by a gradual accumulation of its qualities in a linear fashion, the complex reality of an oscillatory movement in which knowledge struggles to articulate the nature of being via a process close to:
A. Discovering a tention within a pre existing monism with attempts at concealment in order to preserve the original unity.
B. The tention erupting into a polarity which can no longer be suppressed. Attempts to eliminate the polarity by a reduction of one side to the other.
C. A dualism in which the polarity is acknowledged but cleanly separated into two parallel domains.
D. A synthesis that respects the original tention and yet results into a higher unity.
Hans Jonas explains how the various attempts at understanding the nature of being, despite being seemingly contingent products of prolific geniuses at critical junctures in history, still can be viewed as moments of a grand historical dialectic, thus revealing the imminent necessity of their contingent eruption in time.
The rigour and depth of the book in the treatment of its subject matter is matched only in its broad scope that ranges from discussions of the aforementioned problems to a treatment of gnosticism and it's relation with contemporary nihilism and existentialism. This is fitting for a book that re examines the nature of being and man not in terms of the tyranny of abstraction but in the concrete corporeality of man qua man. It affirms the intuition that an analysis of man can only be adequate if it gives voice to his being-in-the-world instead of falling prey to a deficient abstract system that suffers from Whitehead's fallacy of misplaced concreteness.
That being said I disagree with Jonas's contentions with Whitehead's philosophical scheme. Michael Levin's work has shown that postulating the properties of life as universal to 'being' as such with the difference being of degree rather than kind is a valid postulate that is not in conflict with empirical findings, assuming that you take the principle of least action in physics as an exemplar of its minimal yet fundamental incidence in nature.
Finally, by analysing the psychological undercurrents that held sway in the era in which gnosticism sprung up in history, Jonas digs deep underneath the surface mythology of the gnostics and reveals how it sprang from their worldview of alienation from the cosmos. Something being repeated in the modern era after the loss of the horizon of transcendence that was lamented by Nietzsche. It shows how the improper relations of part to whole in which there is a tyrannical supremacy of one side over the other gives way to an ontology of power in which domination can be overcome either by passive resignation to fate as in spinozism / stoicism or rebellious yet frightened self assertion as in existentialism, Heideggerian being-towards-death or gnosticism.
Reading this book was nothing short of an intellectual tour de force. As everything began to fall into place I experienced what can only be described like an aesthetic experience of consummated rational contemplation. To fully appreciate the subtle points of the arguments of this book one should be familiar with basic philosophy but I would recommend it highly to anyone sufficiently curious.