...
Show More
Phänomenologie des Geistes (1807) is G.W.F. Hegel’s first and most important work. It is also arguably his most incomprehensible and mysterious work. I’d go as far as to claim that the book itself is not accessible to anyone who doesn’t understand Kant and the pre-Socratic philosophers. Why? Because Hegel’s magnum opus deals with the questions of Being, Truth and Knowledge and the pre-Socratics (mostly Parmenides and Heraclitus), and especially Kant, are Hegel’s positions in contradistinction to which he develops his own theory.
To understand Hegel’s main ideas, one has only to understand the title of the book: Phenomenology of Mind. It is a study of the phenomena in which the Mind appears to itself. And the ultimate goal, for Hegel, is to understand how absolute knowledge is possible. That is, how is it possible to know the truth of Being – reality as it is itself – without knowing all the particular instances of reality? This is the fundamental quest for Hegel in his Phenomenology and it is a direct reaction to Kant’s system of metaphysics and epistemology.
Kant claimed that, ultimately, the world as it appears to us is a world that we ourselves create. We process sense experiences and in so doing order it in terms of categories – we literally project space, time, causality, quantity, quality, etc. onto the world. Science then studies this phenomenal world as continuously stumbles unto the same old question: What are the underlying principles of this world? This is a false question, Kant says, because we ourselves – or more precise: our Ego as unified Self – create this phenomenal world – we ourselves are the principle of all of science.
But then, if our intellects create the world around us, what does it create it from? The whole Kantian approach starts from the premise that there is sense experience coming in – the raw data, so to speak. Where does this data come from? Well, according to Kant, this emanates from the world as it really is, the world at it is in itself, and which is un-knowable to us. Why? Because our intellects are finite, limited and in itself phenomenal manifestations of this underlying world.
This metaphysical world, the noumenal world, then is postulated as the main spring from which everything develops – Kant sees in this noumenal world the roots of such things as reality, morality and beauty. It is, in a sense, one big metaphysical trash can in which we can throw all the non-sensible (or non-sensical) concepts like God, Immortal Souls, Free Will, etc. etc. and then be content with claiming: these concepts exist, just not in the phenomenal world – the only world we can actually know and say something about – so we should just accept this as a bare fact and be silent.
For Hegel, this whole approach is rather unsatisfying, so he starts off his own quest for True Knowledge from a totally different path.
First off, for Hegel the noumenal world doesn’t exist. He claims that since it is unknowable it is non-existent. This leaves the subjective experience of reality, or to say it in Hegelian fashion “the real is rational; the rational is real” – meaning that is real which is thought and that which is thought is real. So, in a sense, Hegel continues the German Idealism of Fichte, Schelling & co. But in another sense, he discontinues this line of thought. For the Romantic idealists, who radicalized Kant’s idealism, reality was irrational – passionate faith and blind emotions were what’s real – something which Hegel clearly rejects.
So, now to Hegel’s system. Again, the main thing to keep in mind is Hegel’s objective: finding out what’s Truth, how ‘reality’ is. Hegel starts his quest with the most basal, simplistic experience of reality: sense-certainty. I see an object and exclaim: This, here, now! This seems to be pure, unmediated knowledge, but reflection brings us to the problem that ‘now’ and ‘here’ are not particular things, but universal terms. This realization leads the mind to the next stage, which Hegel calls perception. The mind perceives a unified particular object, but then reflection brings to light a new antagonism: while the object seems unified, its characteristics seem to be manifold. So after the antagonism particular-universal we have another antagonism, unity-manifold.
This antagonism is resolved when the mind realizes its own activity is what’s creating these dualism. Hegel call’s this stage understanding. The mind perceives the objective world and it realizes it projects itself unto these objects. For Hegel, force (like in Newton’s universal force of gravitation) is the mind’s projecting unto nature an order. But soon, another dualism arises: the objects are only objects for the mind, and not objects as such. There seems to be an underlying substratum unifying all of the objective world and creating an identity between subject and object(s).
The mind enters the stage of self-certainty. It starts to recognize itself as a source of the existence of objects. It starts to assimilate and appropriate all objects around it, tries to grasp them and in this grasping to ‘own’ them. But pretty soon the mind becomes aware of the fact that there are objects in the world pretty similar to itself, which cannot be assimilated and seem to have the same intention of grasping and assimilating. At the stage enters the infamous master-slave dialectic – but which should really be translated as master (Herr) – aide (Knecht) dialectic.
Anyways, the minds enter a struggle of life and death, seeking recognition of the other minds by destroying them. But in destroying them, this recognition is lost as well. To resolve the antagonism, a master-slave relation arises. The master cuts himself off from the world and sets the slave to work on the objective world for him. This seems to be favourable to the master, but (as always with Hegel) things turn out the reverse: the master grows lazy and doesn’t get the recognition he craves, while the slave submits to the master, assimilates and grasps the world and through this interaction internalizes the master-slave antagonism. This internal strife leads to stoicism (which literally was practices by a slave [Epictetus] and a master [Emperor Marcus Aurelius]) which offers only temporary remittance, since it cuts off the subject from the world. This also holds for religion that promises salvation as well as scepticism, which basically is a retreat from everything altogether. What remains is a unhappy consciousness – it is unhappy since it has Christianity as temporary cure for its internal and external strife, yet it perceives a higher idea of freedom.
Through many dialectical twists and turns the self-conscious mind finds itself identical with nature, with the world. It realizes that the totality, the world, is a unified whole, of which itself is both a particular objects as well as a unified object. This stage Hegel calls Reason. Once Reason is realized, the whole social world comes into play. Reason shows the mind the rational approach to grasping and manipulating the world around it, including itself. This stage is characterized by social phenomena like institutions and social forms of living. Within society the self-conscious mind interacts with other self-conscious minds and is moved from within by reason, in the form of morality, and is restrained and guided from without by the reason, in the form of the state (law, government, religion, etc.).
This state is the final stage in Hegel’s dialectic, which is characterized by the self-conscious mind realizing it is nothing but a partaker in a mind on a higher level, that of the state, and this collective mind (so to speak) is itself part of a historical process in which it clashes with other collective minds (states, civilizations). Through strife and struggle history progresses, and the final destination, the end-goal, is the self-conscious collective mind realizing itself both in itself and for itself. This final stage is the infamous ‘Geist’ (which is non-translatable in my opinion) which as knowledge of both the infinite and the finite, the universal and the particular, of the whole and its parts – in short: it is knowledge of all, absolute knowledge.
So we have here a process of dialectical antagonisms and resolutions on ever higher levels of abstraction, starting from the sense-experience of single unknowing individual and ending with the self-realization of the totality of reality, Geist.
(It is interesting to note that within this dialectical framework Hegel integrates both the conception of reality as the unchanging [Parmenides] and the conception of reality as the changing [Heraclitus]; ending in a conception of reality of both the unchanging and the changing; in Kantian terms: both the noumenal and phenomenal world. The emergence of the idea of the totality, the unity of subject and object, is reality.)
Geist, then, is the emerging end-product of the process of consciousness knowing itself, first partially and finally in totality. This process, of course, can only happen in an existing mind, and reading Phänomenologie des Geistes, one sees the process unfolding itself before one’s eyes. This means that one literally reads Hegel’s own mind climbing the abstract ladder towards absolute knowledge. Since knowledge of totality is both infinite and finite, both subjective and objective, both universal and particular, both undetermined and determined, it is easy to see how Hegel can claim that this is, in essence, God. For Hegel, God is Geist, and Geist is the contemplating mind (of the philosopher, of Hegel) reaching absolute knowledge. So for Hegel, God is a God who is realized through the contemplation of a philosopher.
This certainly is not the God of Christianity, as conceptualized by both Protestants and Catholics, but it resembles in many ways the God of Spinoza, who claimed that God is Nature, hence totality, and every object in the world is a manifestation of a different mode of this Godly substance. But there is one key difference: Spinoza was a materialist and hence could identify God with material Nature, while Hegel’s God is only an idea, emerging from a process in which a mind grasps ever more abstract and including ideas.
And this final conclusion leads me immediately to some important remarks on Hegel’s philosophy.
First, Hegel’s metaphysical system was received by contemporary and subsequent philosophers in different ways, but in general there are three lines of direct development here. (1) Schopenhauer rejected Hegel’s main principle (Geist) altogether and claimed the main principle of metaphysics was the Will to life, while Nietzsche developed Schopenhauer’s Will into the Will to Power. While Schopenhauer claimed the response to this Will should be denial, Nietzsche claimed the proper response is acting on this Will. (2) Kierkegaard (although I have only superficial knowledge of his ideas) claimed Hegel worked out his system and then sat down beside it. What he meant was that Hegel’s system is an empty formalism; it lacked any opportunity for people to participate in it – it is conceptual theology. For Kierkegaard God should be believed in, we should make the leap of faith. (3) Then we have Karl Marx who, inspired by Ludwig Feuerbach’s theology, claimed that religion is just a projection which blinds man to the fact that reality is ‘acting’ in this world. History is the progress of human action, driven by human instincts and desires. Hegel claimed that ideas determine the world, but in truth the world determines ideas.
All three lines of development are unique, but have in common that they find Hegel’s philosophical system of the world to be empty, abstract and formal. All three lines of development claim that existence precedes essence (as in perception of objects and determining their essence). This realization, that reason (even logic and mathematics) is not the first step in knowledge, is fundamental in the development of continental philosophy. Edmund Husserl, for example, develops his tremendously influential phenomenological method as a scientific method to grasp the pre-scientific world, the world that is the foundation of reason. In this sense, Hegel is the last metaphysical, systematic philosopher and self-destructs this whole philosophical attempt, leaving existentialism and phenomenology as two future orphans.
Second, Hegel is often criticized by people for his aim to develop a system of totality, a system that encompasses the totality of things and that is rigid and determinate. These critics often aim their arrows at Hegel’s philosophy of right (his view on the perfect state) and partially his philosophy of history (his view of historicism, history following deterministic laws). It is easy to see how people see in Hegel’s blueprint for the ideal state an attempt to subjugate individuals and to only count development on the state level. And to be fair, throughout all of Hegel’s philosophy is the continuous attempt to resolve particulars into universals and to see highest, loftiest stages of Geist on the level of states and, ultimately, God.
In short, Hegel discounts concrete individuals and seems to be only concerned with abstract total ideas – when he is concerned with freedom, he is not concerned with individual freedom (individuals have to offer themselves on the altar of history) but with the abstract idea of freedom in the state on the world-political stage. For Hegel, “Das Wahre ist das Ganze” – the real is the whole.
Hegel’s philosophy is a totalitarian system in that it seeks to subjugate all particulars and lower levels with the aim of reaching a final goal (i.e. the realization of something absolute). In this sense, it is a blueprint for the later totalitarian systems in politics, although to be fair to Hegel, the tendency to completely eradicate the individual and to offer them for the greater good or God has been with us throughout our history. And ultimately, you can’t hold someone responsible for the acts of someone else, especially a future someone else. (The same type of senseless critique is often levelled at Darwin in relation to social Darwinism and Nazi eugenics, and Nietzsche in relation to Nazi ideology.)
Third, and this is my main problem with Hegel, is that he commends contradiction. Contradiction always was used as a formal criterion to separate senseless from sensible concepts. Something that is internally contradicted or contradicted by something external cannot be true. With Hegel this formal criterion of truth is not only done away with but is actually reversed: now truth is that which can be contradicted!
Hegel’s conception of knowledge is the dialectical process in which contradictions are integrated in new contradictions on a more abstract level. So Hegel actively seeks out contradictions to discover truth and he seems so obsessed by contradictions that he seems to see them everywhere – meaning he contradicts certain things that are nonsensical to contradict (more on that in the next remark).
So from Hegel onwards we see a destructive trend developing in philosophy where truth is not to be looked for through rigorous analysis but, in ultimo, in everything. Nietzsche’s perspectivism is already a faint glimmer (truth does not exist, all that exist are perceptions from different perspectives) but postmodern philosophy is the real fraud here. This school of philosophy radically dismantles all truths and ends with the relativistic claim that truth is nothing but the power of some person or group over others. Truth becomes a question of discrimination and now, anno 2019, we have women’s studies, black history and gender studies – along with the denial of scientific claims and the erosion of public trust in science.
Anyway, back to the review. A fourth and final remark is the imaginary relations Hegel seems to see between all kinds of different phenomena. He starts off with sense experience and ends up with a theory of how states battle it out on the world-historical stage and end in the philosopher grasping absolute knowledge. Admittedly, this is a simplistic and slightly caricaturistic representation of Hegel, but ultimately it *is* what Hegel is doing. He continuously moves from the particular, the individual to generality and when he has reached his destination, a new individuality, this time on a higher level, pops up, to allow him to repeat this process. In short: Hegel sees contradictions and generalizations everywhere.
This generality allows him to parallel his theory of the developing self-consciousness with history (for example, seeing the stage of Reason being manifested in the period Reformation-French Revolution), but this at once makes his philosophical system so vague and so speculative that it fails miserably in convincing us of the truth of Hegel’s claims. Hegel was a man who knew what he wanted to find before he set out on his quest for truth, this is why he ends up with his own grasp of absolute knowledge as both God and the destination of World-History. This is why he had to develop his own system of logic, basically one huge apology for using the dialectical method. This is why literally everything in the world, from science to state government and from sense-experience to religion, fits neatly into one grand system.
I cannot conclude otherwise but Hegel was either a very solipsistic individual, an autistic person (who views himself as literally the centre of everything and mostly uses reason to manoeuvre through life), a Lutheran apologist (who had to re-create a place for God after the Enlightenment and Kant), or else a philosophical charlatan. I don’t know which one of the options it was, but Hegel’s philosophy is so speculative that it borders the absurd – I honestly don’t understand how this way of doing philosophy has found so many followers over the years. And this is the feeling I get every time I try to understand (open-mindedly) one of the most renowned of these continental philosophers. I understand their goals, their methods and their perspective on philosophy, even their answers, but I simply don’t get the point. It seems to me to be much ado about nothing…
As for Hegel: I can see the attractiveness and even beautify of his philosophical system, but we should not forget that he set out this whole undertaking in order to answer the questions of Truth and Knowledge. And we shouldn’t forget his severe criticisms of Kant and the German idealists either. Whereas Kant was someone who seems to be rigid yet honest, Hegel seems to be flexible and fraudulent. He simply doesn’t deliver on his promises. He offers such a speculative system and ambiguous method, that basically anything can be fitted into it and which can explain everything.
This is not philosophy; this is theology. Add to this fact that this is a 500 page book which is written in such an absurd and incomprehensible style, that it is very hard to see how this book deserves a recommendation, let alone a reading attempt. No I simply detest this book and I find it truly bothersome – I am glad I am done with it and I am glad I have grasped Hegel’s system to such an extent that I will never have to read him anymore. Sorry to end this review on such a sour note, so to end with a more positive fact: I am done, yeah!
To understand Hegel’s main ideas, one has only to understand the title of the book: Phenomenology of Mind. It is a study of the phenomena in which the Mind appears to itself. And the ultimate goal, for Hegel, is to understand how absolute knowledge is possible. That is, how is it possible to know the truth of Being – reality as it is itself – without knowing all the particular instances of reality? This is the fundamental quest for Hegel in his Phenomenology and it is a direct reaction to Kant’s system of metaphysics and epistemology.
Kant claimed that, ultimately, the world as it appears to us is a world that we ourselves create. We process sense experiences and in so doing order it in terms of categories – we literally project space, time, causality, quantity, quality, etc. onto the world. Science then studies this phenomenal world as continuously stumbles unto the same old question: What are the underlying principles of this world? This is a false question, Kant says, because we ourselves – or more precise: our Ego as unified Self – create this phenomenal world – we ourselves are the principle of all of science.
But then, if our intellects create the world around us, what does it create it from? The whole Kantian approach starts from the premise that there is sense experience coming in – the raw data, so to speak. Where does this data come from? Well, according to Kant, this emanates from the world as it really is, the world at it is in itself, and which is un-knowable to us. Why? Because our intellects are finite, limited and in itself phenomenal manifestations of this underlying world.
This metaphysical world, the noumenal world, then is postulated as the main spring from which everything develops – Kant sees in this noumenal world the roots of such things as reality, morality and beauty. It is, in a sense, one big metaphysical trash can in which we can throw all the non-sensible (or non-sensical) concepts like God, Immortal Souls, Free Will, etc. etc. and then be content with claiming: these concepts exist, just not in the phenomenal world – the only world we can actually know and say something about – so we should just accept this as a bare fact and be silent.
For Hegel, this whole approach is rather unsatisfying, so he starts off his own quest for True Knowledge from a totally different path.
First off, for Hegel the noumenal world doesn’t exist. He claims that since it is unknowable it is non-existent. This leaves the subjective experience of reality, or to say it in Hegelian fashion “the real is rational; the rational is real” – meaning that is real which is thought and that which is thought is real. So, in a sense, Hegel continues the German Idealism of Fichte, Schelling & co. But in another sense, he discontinues this line of thought. For the Romantic idealists, who radicalized Kant’s idealism, reality was irrational – passionate faith and blind emotions were what’s real – something which Hegel clearly rejects.
So, now to Hegel’s system. Again, the main thing to keep in mind is Hegel’s objective: finding out what’s Truth, how ‘reality’ is. Hegel starts his quest with the most basal, simplistic experience of reality: sense-certainty. I see an object and exclaim: This, here, now! This seems to be pure, unmediated knowledge, but reflection brings us to the problem that ‘now’ and ‘here’ are not particular things, but universal terms. This realization leads the mind to the next stage, which Hegel calls perception. The mind perceives a unified particular object, but then reflection brings to light a new antagonism: while the object seems unified, its characteristics seem to be manifold. So after the antagonism particular-universal we have another antagonism, unity-manifold.
This antagonism is resolved when the mind realizes its own activity is what’s creating these dualism. Hegel call’s this stage understanding. The mind perceives the objective world and it realizes it projects itself unto these objects. For Hegel, force (like in Newton’s universal force of gravitation) is the mind’s projecting unto nature an order. But soon, another dualism arises: the objects are only objects for the mind, and not objects as such. There seems to be an underlying substratum unifying all of the objective world and creating an identity between subject and object(s).
The mind enters the stage of self-certainty. It starts to recognize itself as a source of the existence of objects. It starts to assimilate and appropriate all objects around it, tries to grasp them and in this grasping to ‘own’ them. But pretty soon the mind becomes aware of the fact that there are objects in the world pretty similar to itself, which cannot be assimilated and seem to have the same intention of grasping and assimilating. At the stage enters the infamous master-slave dialectic – but which should really be translated as master (Herr) – aide (Knecht) dialectic.
Anyways, the minds enter a struggle of life and death, seeking recognition of the other minds by destroying them. But in destroying them, this recognition is lost as well. To resolve the antagonism, a master-slave relation arises. The master cuts himself off from the world and sets the slave to work on the objective world for him. This seems to be favourable to the master, but (as always with Hegel) things turn out the reverse: the master grows lazy and doesn’t get the recognition he craves, while the slave submits to the master, assimilates and grasps the world and through this interaction internalizes the master-slave antagonism. This internal strife leads to stoicism (which literally was practices by a slave [Epictetus] and a master [Emperor Marcus Aurelius]) which offers only temporary remittance, since it cuts off the subject from the world. This also holds for religion that promises salvation as well as scepticism, which basically is a retreat from everything altogether. What remains is a unhappy consciousness – it is unhappy since it has Christianity as temporary cure for its internal and external strife, yet it perceives a higher idea of freedom.
Through many dialectical twists and turns the self-conscious mind finds itself identical with nature, with the world. It realizes that the totality, the world, is a unified whole, of which itself is both a particular objects as well as a unified object. This stage Hegel calls Reason. Once Reason is realized, the whole social world comes into play. Reason shows the mind the rational approach to grasping and manipulating the world around it, including itself. This stage is characterized by social phenomena like institutions and social forms of living. Within society the self-conscious mind interacts with other self-conscious minds and is moved from within by reason, in the form of morality, and is restrained and guided from without by the reason, in the form of the state (law, government, religion, etc.).
This state is the final stage in Hegel’s dialectic, which is characterized by the self-conscious mind realizing it is nothing but a partaker in a mind on a higher level, that of the state, and this collective mind (so to speak) is itself part of a historical process in which it clashes with other collective minds (states, civilizations). Through strife and struggle history progresses, and the final destination, the end-goal, is the self-conscious collective mind realizing itself both in itself and for itself. This final stage is the infamous ‘Geist’ (which is non-translatable in my opinion) which as knowledge of both the infinite and the finite, the universal and the particular, of the whole and its parts – in short: it is knowledge of all, absolute knowledge.
So we have here a process of dialectical antagonisms and resolutions on ever higher levels of abstraction, starting from the sense-experience of single unknowing individual and ending with the self-realization of the totality of reality, Geist.
(It is interesting to note that within this dialectical framework Hegel integrates both the conception of reality as the unchanging [Parmenides] and the conception of reality as the changing [Heraclitus]; ending in a conception of reality of both the unchanging and the changing; in Kantian terms: both the noumenal and phenomenal world. The emergence of the idea of the totality, the unity of subject and object, is reality.)
Geist, then, is the emerging end-product of the process of consciousness knowing itself, first partially and finally in totality. This process, of course, can only happen in an existing mind, and reading Phänomenologie des Geistes, one sees the process unfolding itself before one’s eyes. This means that one literally reads Hegel’s own mind climbing the abstract ladder towards absolute knowledge. Since knowledge of totality is both infinite and finite, both subjective and objective, both universal and particular, both undetermined and determined, it is easy to see how Hegel can claim that this is, in essence, God. For Hegel, God is Geist, and Geist is the contemplating mind (of the philosopher, of Hegel) reaching absolute knowledge. So for Hegel, God is a God who is realized through the contemplation of a philosopher.
This certainly is not the God of Christianity, as conceptualized by both Protestants and Catholics, but it resembles in many ways the God of Spinoza, who claimed that God is Nature, hence totality, and every object in the world is a manifestation of a different mode of this Godly substance. But there is one key difference: Spinoza was a materialist and hence could identify God with material Nature, while Hegel’s God is only an idea, emerging from a process in which a mind grasps ever more abstract and including ideas.
And this final conclusion leads me immediately to some important remarks on Hegel’s philosophy.
First, Hegel’s metaphysical system was received by contemporary and subsequent philosophers in different ways, but in general there are three lines of direct development here. (1) Schopenhauer rejected Hegel’s main principle (Geist) altogether and claimed the main principle of metaphysics was the Will to life, while Nietzsche developed Schopenhauer’s Will into the Will to Power. While Schopenhauer claimed the response to this Will should be denial, Nietzsche claimed the proper response is acting on this Will. (2) Kierkegaard (although I have only superficial knowledge of his ideas) claimed Hegel worked out his system and then sat down beside it. What he meant was that Hegel’s system is an empty formalism; it lacked any opportunity for people to participate in it – it is conceptual theology. For Kierkegaard God should be believed in, we should make the leap of faith. (3) Then we have Karl Marx who, inspired by Ludwig Feuerbach’s theology, claimed that religion is just a projection which blinds man to the fact that reality is ‘acting’ in this world. History is the progress of human action, driven by human instincts and desires. Hegel claimed that ideas determine the world, but in truth the world determines ideas.
All three lines of development are unique, but have in common that they find Hegel’s philosophical system of the world to be empty, abstract and formal. All three lines of development claim that existence precedes essence (as in perception of objects and determining their essence). This realization, that reason (even logic and mathematics) is not the first step in knowledge, is fundamental in the development of continental philosophy. Edmund Husserl, for example, develops his tremendously influential phenomenological method as a scientific method to grasp the pre-scientific world, the world that is the foundation of reason. In this sense, Hegel is the last metaphysical, systematic philosopher and self-destructs this whole philosophical attempt, leaving existentialism and phenomenology as two future orphans.
Second, Hegel is often criticized by people for his aim to develop a system of totality, a system that encompasses the totality of things and that is rigid and determinate. These critics often aim their arrows at Hegel’s philosophy of right (his view on the perfect state) and partially his philosophy of history (his view of historicism, history following deterministic laws). It is easy to see how people see in Hegel’s blueprint for the ideal state an attempt to subjugate individuals and to only count development on the state level. And to be fair, throughout all of Hegel’s philosophy is the continuous attempt to resolve particulars into universals and to see highest, loftiest stages of Geist on the level of states and, ultimately, God.
In short, Hegel discounts concrete individuals and seems to be only concerned with abstract total ideas – when he is concerned with freedom, he is not concerned with individual freedom (individuals have to offer themselves on the altar of history) but with the abstract idea of freedom in the state on the world-political stage. For Hegel, “Das Wahre ist das Ganze” – the real is the whole.
Hegel’s philosophy is a totalitarian system in that it seeks to subjugate all particulars and lower levels with the aim of reaching a final goal (i.e. the realization of something absolute). In this sense, it is a blueprint for the later totalitarian systems in politics, although to be fair to Hegel, the tendency to completely eradicate the individual and to offer them for the greater good or God has been with us throughout our history. And ultimately, you can’t hold someone responsible for the acts of someone else, especially a future someone else. (The same type of senseless critique is often levelled at Darwin in relation to social Darwinism and Nazi eugenics, and Nietzsche in relation to Nazi ideology.)
Third, and this is my main problem with Hegel, is that he commends contradiction. Contradiction always was used as a formal criterion to separate senseless from sensible concepts. Something that is internally contradicted or contradicted by something external cannot be true. With Hegel this formal criterion of truth is not only done away with but is actually reversed: now truth is that which can be contradicted!
Hegel’s conception of knowledge is the dialectical process in which contradictions are integrated in new contradictions on a more abstract level. So Hegel actively seeks out contradictions to discover truth and he seems so obsessed by contradictions that he seems to see them everywhere – meaning he contradicts certain things that are nonsensical to contradict (more on that in the next remark).
So from Hegel onwards we see a destructive trend developing in philosophy where truth is not to be looked for through rigorous analysis but, in ultimo, in everything. Nietzsche’s perspectivism is already a faint glimmer (truth does not exist, all that exist are perceptions from different perspectives) but postmodern philosophy is the real fraud here. This school of philosophy radically dismantles all truths and ends with the relativistic claim that truth is nothing but the power of some person or group over others. Truth becomes a question of discrimination and now, anno 2019, we have women’s studies, black history and gender studies – along with the denial of scientific claims and the erosion of public trust in science.
Anyway, back to the review. A fourth and final remark is the imaginary relations Hegel seems to see between all kinds of different phenomena. He starts off with sense experience and ends up with a theory of how states battle it out on the world-historical stage and end in the philosopher grasping absolute knowledge. Admittedly, this is a simplistic and slightly caricaturistic representation of Hegel, but ultimately it *is* what Hegel is doing. He continuously moves from the particular, the individual to generality and when he has reached his destination, a new individuality, this time on a higher level, pops up, to allow him to repeat this process. In short: Hegel sees contradictions and generalizations everywhere.
This generality allows him to parallel his theory of the developing self-consciousness with history (for example, seeing the stage of Reason being manifested in the period Reformation-French Revolution), but this at once makes his philosophical system so vague and so speculative that it fails miserably in convincing us of the truth of Hegel’s claims. Hegel was a man who knew what he wanted to find before he set out on his quest for truth, this is why he ends up with his own grasp of absolute knowledge as both God and the destination of World-History. This is why he had to develop his own system of logic, basically one huge apology for using the dialectical method. This is why literally everything in the world, from science to state government and from sense-experience to religion, fits neatly into one grand system.
I cannot conclude otherwise but Hegel was either a very solipsistic individual, an autistic person (who views himself as literally the centre of everything and mostly uses reason to manoeuvre through life), a Lutheran apologist (who had to re-create a place for God after the Enlightenment and Kant), or else a philosophical charlatan. I don’t know which one of the options it was, but Hegel’s philosophy is so speculative that it borders the absurd – I honestly don’t understand how this way of doing philosophy has found so many followers over the years. And this is the feeling I get every time I try to understand (open-mindedly) one of the most renowned of these continental philosophers. I understand their goals, their methods and their perspective on philosophy, even their answers, but I simply don’t get the point. It seems to me to be much ado about nothing…
As for Hegel: I can see the attractiveness and even beautify of his philosophical system, but we should not forget that he set out this whole undertaking in order to answer the questions of Truth and Knowledge. And we shouldn’t forget his severe criticisms of Kant and the German idealists either. Whereas Kant was someone who seems to be rigid yet honest, Hegel seems to be flexible and fraudulent. He simply doesn’t deliver on his promises. He offers such a speculative system and ambiguous method, that basically anything can be fitted into it and which can explain everything.
This is not philosophy; this is theology. Add to this fact that this is a 500 page book which is written in such an absurd and incomprehensible style, that it is very hard to see how this book deserves a recommendation, let alone a reading attempt. No I simply detest this book and I find it truly bothersome – I am glad I am done with it and I am glad I have grasped Hegel’s system to such an extent that I will never have to read him anymore. Sorry to end this review on such a sour note, so to end with a more positive fact: I am done, yeah!