...
Show More
While the Gorgias gets off to a dull start, it turns out to be one of the best—and by far the funniest—of Plato’s dialogues. Socrates takes on a party of sophistic rhetoricians, demonstrating that the “discipline” of rhetoric, when used for any purpose but to identify and advance the good, is no discipline at all, but only a form of flattery—analogous to “cookery” and “ornamentation”—which corrupts the life of the city. True statesmanship is not about persuasion, flowery speeches, or getting one’s way, but is fundamentally concerned with the moral rectitude and self-discipline of one’s people, and seeks above all else to protect them from the immorality that threatens their happiness. Since he alone recognizes that statecraft is soulcraft, Socrates proves to be the only true statesman that Athens has ever had; and this, ironically, is what will inevitably make him a target of state persecution. “My trial”, he says, “will be equivalent to a doctor being prosecuted by a cook before a jury of young children.” The bitter, effervescent medicine will be scorned in favor of the savory, corrosive dessert. But this is of little concern to one intent on happiness—in this life and the next.
SOCRATES: I’ll review the whole argument so far. Is the pleasant the same as the good? No, they’re different. Callicles and I agreed on that.
Should the good be the reason we do pleasant things, or the pleasant be the reason we do good things? The good should be the reason we do pleasant things.
Isn’t it the quality of being pleasant which makes us enjoy things, and the quality of being good which makes us good? Yes.
Now, what does it take to be a good human being? What does it take to be a good anything, in fact? It always takes a specific state of goodness, doesn’t it? I don’t see how we can deny that, Callicles.
And whether we’re talking about a good artefact, a good body, a good mind for that matter, or a good creature, what it takes for these states of goodness to occur in an ideal form is not chaos, but organization and perfection and the particular branch of expertise whose province the object in question is. Right? I agree.
In every case, then, a good state is an organized and orderly state, isn’t it? I’d say so. So a thing has to be informed by a particular orderly structure—the structure appropriate to it—to be good, doesn’t it? I think so.
Doesn’t it follow that a mind possessed of its proper structure is better than a disordered mind? It’s bound to be.
But a ‘mind possessed of orderly structure’ is an orderly mind, isn’t it? Naturally.
And an orderly mind is a self-disciplined mind? Absolutely.
From which it follows that a self-disciplined mind is a good mind. Now, I can’t see anything wrong with this argument, Callicles, but if you can, please tell me what it is.
CALLICLES: Just get on with it, Socrates.
SOCRATES: All right. If a self-disciplined mind is good, then a mind in the opposite state is bad. In other words, an undisciplined and self-indulgent mind is bad. Yes.
Now, a disciplined person must act in an appropriate manner towards both gods and his fellow human beings, because inappropriate behaviour indicates lack of self-discipline. Yes, that’s bound to be so.
Well, when ‘appropriate’ is used of the way we relate to our fellow human beings, it means ‘just’; and when it's applied to the way we relate to the gods, it means ‘religious'. And, of course, anyone who acts justly and religiously is a just and religious person. True.
He's also bound to have courage, because a disciplined person doesn’t choose inappropriate objects to seek out or avoid. No, he turns towards or away from events, people, pleasures, and irritations as and when he should, and steadily endures what he should endure. It follows, Callicles, that because a self-disciplined person is just, brave, and religious, as we’ve explained, he’s a paradigm of goodness. Now, a good person is bound to do whatever he does well and successfully, and success brings fulfillment and happiness, whereas a bad man does badly and is therefore unhappy. Unhappiness, then, is the lot of someone who’s the opposite of self-disciplined—in other words, the kind of self-indulgent person you were championing.
That’s my position, and I believe it to be true. If it really is true, it looks as though anyone who wants to be happy must seek out and practice self-discipline, and beat as hasty a retreat as possible away from self-indulgence. The best course would be for him to see to it that he never has to be restrained, but if he or anyone close to him…does ever need it, then he must let justice and restraint be imposed, or else forfeit happiness.
I’ll tell you what the ideal is that we should set ourselves to live by, in my opinion. We should devote all our own and our community’s energies towards ensuring the presence of justice and self-discipline, and so guaranteeing happiness. That’s what should guide our actions. We shouldn’t refuse to restrain our desires, because that condemns us to a life of endlessly trying to satisfy them. And this is the life of a predatory outlaw, in the sense that anyone who lives like that will never be on good terms with anyone else—any other human being, let alone a god—since he’s incapable of co-operation, and co-operation is a prerequisite for friendship. In fact, Callicles, the experts’ opinion is that co-operation, love, order, discipline, and justice bind heaven and earth, gods and men. That’s why they call the universe an ordered whole, my friend, rather than a disorderly mess or an unruly shambles. . . . [We] should denounce any wrongs committed not only by ourselves, but even by our family and friends…this is what rhetoric should be used for.
SOCRATES: I’ll review the whole argument so far. Is the pleasant the same as the good? No, they’re different. Callicles and I agreed on that.
Should the good be the reason we do pleasant things, or the pleasant be the reason we do good things? The good should be the reason we do pleasant things.
Isn’t it the quality of being pleasant which makes us enjoy things, and the quality of being good which makes us good? Yes.
Now, what does it take to be a good human being? What does it take to be a good anything, in fact? It always takes a specific state of goodness, doesn’t it? I don’t see how we can deny that, Callicles.
And whether we’re talking about a good artefact, a good body, a good mind for that matter, or a good creature, what it takes for these states of goodness to occur in an ideal form is not chaos, but organization and perfection and the particular branch of expertise whose province the object in question is. Right? I agree.
In every case, then, a good state is an organized and orderly state, isn’t it? I’d say so. So a thing has to be informed by a particular orderly structure—the structure appropriate to it—to be good, doesn’t it? I think so.
Doesn’t it follow that a mind possessed of its proper structure is better than a disordered mind? It’s bound to be.
But a ‘mind possessed of orderly structure’ is an orderly mind, isn’t it? Naturally.
And an orderly mind is a self-disciplined mind? Absolutely.
From which it follows that a self-disciplined mind is a good mind. Now, I can’t see anything wrong with this argument, Callicles, but if you can, please tell me what it is.
CALLICLES: Just get on with it, Socrates.
SOCRATES: All right. If a self-disciplined mind is good, then a mind in the opposite state is bad. In other words, an undisciplined and self-indulgent mind is bad. Yes.
Now, a disciplined person must act in an appropriate manner towards both gods and his fellow human beings, because inappropriate behaviour indicates lack of self-discipline. Yes, that’s bound to be so.
Well, when ‘appropriate’ is used of the way we relate to our fellow human beings, it means ‘just’; and when it's applied to the way we relate to the gods, it means ‘religious'. And, of course, anyone who acts justly and religiously is a just and religious person. True.
He's also bound to have courage, because a disciplined person doesn’t choose inappropriate objects to seek out or avoid. No, he turns towards or away from events, people, pleasures, and irritations as and when he should, and steadily endures what he should endure. It follows, Callicles, that because a self-disciplined person is just, brave, and religious, as we’ve explained, he’s a paradigm of goodness. Now, a good person is bound to do whatever he does well and successfully, and success brings fulfillment and happiness, whereas a bad man does badly and is therefore unhappy. Unhappiness, then, is the lot of someone who’s the opposite of self-disciplined—in other words, the kind of self-indulgent person you were championing.
That’s my position, and I believe it to be true. If it really is true, it looks as though anyone who wants to be happy must seek out and practice self-discipline, and beat as hasty a retreat as possible away from self-indulgence. The best course would be for him to see to it that he never has to be restrained, but if he or anyone close to him…does ever need it, then he must let justice and restraint be imposed, or else forfeit happiness.
I’ll tell you what the ideal is that we should set ourselves to live by, in my opinion. We should devote all our own and our community’s energies towards ensuring the presence of justice and self-discipline, and so guaranteeing happiness. That’s what should guide our actions. We shouldn’t refuse to restrain our desires, because that condemns us to a life of endlessly trying to satisfy them. And this is the life of a predatory outlaw, in the sense that anyone who lives like that will never be on good terms with anyone else—any other human being, let alone a god—since he’s incapable of co-operation, and co-operation is a prerequisite for friendship. In fact, Callicles, the experts’ opinion is that co-operation, love, order, discipline, and justice bind heaven and earth, gods and men. That’s why they call the universe an ordered whole, my friend, rather than a disorderly mess or an unruly shambles. . . . [We] should denounce any wrongs committed not only by ourselves, but even by our family and friends…this is what rhetoric should be used for.