...
Show More
Dennett invited us to reconsider fundamental aspects of human experience. Seems fitting post landmark intro session - will need a re-read later on.
Ultimately, it opens up new ways of thinking about memory, decision-making, and the nature of self. If our conscious experience is a constantly edited narrative, what does this mean for our sense of free will, or our understanding of personal identity?
In short:
- In the 17th century, René Descartes proposed that the mind and body were separate entities, with the pineal gland serving as their connection. This concept of a central control point in the brain persisted, stopping our understanding for centuries. As neuroscience progressed, researchers eagerly sought this seat of consciousness, expecting to find a specific region where our experiences come together and decisions are made. But a curious thing happened. The more we learned about the brain, the more this idea of a central consciousness hub began to crumble. Different aspects of our experience—sight, sound, emotion, memory— seemed to be processed in various parts of the brain, often simultaneously.
- In other words, there was no single centre of consciousness to be found.
Notes:
- From Descartes' mind-body problem to modern neuroscience, the question of consciousness has long been shrouded in mystery.
- what if consciousness, the very essence of being, is just an elaborate illusion?
- Instead, he proposed that our experience of consciousness is more like a constantly edited, crowdsourced conglomeration than a unified self.
- The Multiple Drafts Model This theory challenged the notion of a singular, coherent stream of consciousness, in which humans had long believed, in favour of a chaotic inner turbulence of competing realities or interpretations of events.
- These drafts aren't neatly ordered or centrally coordinated either. Instead, they compete for dominance, with the winning draft becoming our conscious experience. This process happens continuously, and so rapidly that it gives the illusion of a smooth, unified consciousness.
- Rather than faithfully recording events as they happen, our brain constructs a coherent narrative after the fact, filling in details retroactively. This model had profound implications. It suggested that there's no single moment when something enters our consciousness. Instead, consciousness emerges from the ongoing process of narrative creation and revision in our brains.
- He proposed that language wasn't just a tool for expressing thoughts, but a fundamental shaper of consciousness itself.
- While animals might have rich sensory experiences, Dennett proposed that without language, they lack the kind of reflective narrative consciousness that humans possess. It challenged us to reconsider the nature of thought, self, and the very essence of what it means to be consciously aware.
Developed by philosophers like Edmund Husserl and later Maurice Merleau-Ponty, phenomenology is the study of conscious experience from the first-person point of view. It aims to describe what it's like to have certain experiences, focusing on the subjective, lived reality of consciousness. However, this introspective method faced a significant challenge from the start.
The experience of consciousness is as personal and subjective as consciousness itself. Enter Dennett's innovative solution, heterophenomenology. Heterophenomenology, which means the phenomenology of another, was Dennett's attempt to bridge the gap between subjective experience and objective science.
Heterophenomenology had far-reaching implications. It suggested that our intuitions about our own consciousness might be flawed or incomplete. Just as we can be mistaken about the causes of our behaviour, we might be mistaken about the very nature of our conscious experiences.
Dennett compared our sense of free will to a benign illusion, like the impression that the sun moves across the sky instead of the earth turning, as the sun remains stationary.
Dennett saw the self as a convenient fiction our brains construct to make sense of our experiences. Imagine writing your autobiography.
If our decisions emerge from complex brain processes rather than a central, controlling self, how does this affect our concepts of moral responsibility?
Ultimately, it opens up new ways of thinking about memory, decision-making, and the nature of self. If our conscious experience is a constantly edited narrative, what does this mean for our sense of free will, or our understanding of personal identity?
In short:
- In the 17th century, René Descartes proposed that the mind and body were separate entities, with the pineal gland serving as their connection. This concept of a central control point in the brain persisted, stopping our understanding for centuries. As neuroscience progressed, researchers eagerly sought this seat of consciousness, expecting to find a specific region where our experiences come together and decisions are made. But a curious thing happened. The more we learned about the brain, the more this idea of a central consciousness hub began to crumble. Different aspects of our experience—sight, sound, emotion, memory— seemed to be processed in various parts of the brain, often simultaneously.
- In other words, there was no single centre of consciousness to be found.
Notes:
- From Descartes' mind-body problem to modern neuroscience, the question of consciousness has long been shrouded in mystery.
- what if consciousness, the very essence of being, is just an elaborate illusion?
- Instead, he proposed that our experience of consciousness is more like a constantly edited, crowdsourced conglomeration than a unified self.
- The Multiple Drafts Model This theory challenged the notion of a singular, coherent stream of consciousness, in which humans had long believed, in favour of a chaotic inner turbulence of competing realities or interpretations of events.
- These drafts aren't neatly ordered or centrally coordinated either. Instead, they compete for dominance, with the winning draft becoming our conscious experience. This process happens continuously, and so rapidly that it gives the illusion of a smooth, unified consciousness.
- Rather than faithfully recording events as they happen, our brain constructs a coherent narrative after the fact, filling in details retroactively. This model had profound implications. It suggested that there's no single moment when something enters our consciousness. Instead, consciousness emerges from the ongoing process of narrative creation and revision in our brains.
- He proposed that language wasn't just a tool for expressing thoughts, but a fundamental shaper of consciousness itself.
- While animals might have rich sensory experiences, Dennett proposed that without language, they lack the kind of reflective narrative consciousness that humans possess. It challenged us to reconsider the nature of thought, self, and the very essence of what it means to be consciously aware.
Developed by philosophers like Edmund Husserl and later Maurice Merleau-Ponty, phenomenology is the study of conscious experience from the first-person point of view. It aims to describe what it's like to have certain experiences, focusing on the subjective, lived reality of consciousness. However, this introspective method faced a significant challenge from the start.
The experience of consciousness is as personal and subjective as consciousness itself. Enter Dennett's innovative solution, heterophenomenology. Heterophenomenology, which means the phenomenology of another, was Dennett's attempt to bridge the gap between subjective experience and objective science.
Heterophenomenology had far-reaching implications. It suggested that our intuitions about our own consciousness might be flawed or incomplete. Just as we can be mistaken about the causes of our behaviour, we might be mistaken about the very nature of our conscious experiences.
Dennett compared our sense of free will to a benign illusion, like the impression that the sun moves across the sky instead of the earth turning, as the sun remains stationary.
Dennett saw the self as a convenient fiction our brains construct to make sense of our experiences. Imagine writing your autobiography.
If our decisions emerge from complex brain processes rather than a central, controlling self, how does this affect our concepts of moral responsibility?