Community Reviews

Rating(3.9 / 5.0, 100 votes)
5 stars
23(23%)
4 stars
44(44%)
3 stars
33(33%)
2 stars
0(0%)
1 stars
0(0%)
100 reviews
April 1,2025
... Show More
This is one of those books that is so imposing that the subdivisions of the book are themselves books, like with Paradise Lost. This has fifteen books, and so I figure that if I understand one fifteenth of each section, I'll have the equivalent of one impressive book read.
April 1,2025
... Show More
I cannot believe I read this book. THE WHOLE THING. Wow. I respect the effort, I really do, but dude that was BORING. *Laugh’s like Nelson*
April 1,2025
... Show More
Rarely have I been so aware that this book is reading me, rather than I reading it.
April 1,2025
... Show More
One of the most thought-proviking and impressive works by Saint Augustin...

April 1,2025
... Show More
Saint Hilary, Bishop of Poitiers around 350 AD. This man wrote a 565 page refutation of Arianism. The book is long, at times it can be difficult to wade through but it is profitable. Although by the title one may think that this deals with the Trinity (& it does in a limited sense) the main thrust of the book is to prove & clearly demonstrate the divinity of Christ. This book is really good.

Hilary begins by stating a difficulty; that human language & thought cannot cope with the Infinite. He also s points out that the Arians in their creed asserted one true God, but, they would argue that Christ is indeed God, but of a nature different from that of the Father. In refutation of this Hilary goes through the history of creation, proving that the narrative reveals not only the Son's share in that work, but also His equality & oneness of nature with the Father; in other words, that He is not only God but true God. In fact Hilary works his way through the entire Old & New Testaments as he tirelessly shows that all of scripture is in agreement with the truth that Jesus is eternally the Son of God, & that He is God of very God.

There are times when Hilary makes some strong comments about the honesty & ethics of the arguments & motives of the Arians. He says in one place “Theological differences are not the result of honest reasoning, but of reasoning distorted, as in the case of these Arians, by preconceived opinions, whose cause is sin & their result hypocrisy.”

You need to tread carefully & read thoroughly when Hilary uses phrases as “true faith asserts that God is born from God,” When he uses such phrases in speaking of God the Son being born of God he is not saying Jesus became the Son at His incarnation (but he does assert that at the incarnation it was God of very God taking on human flesh) & he is not saying the Jesus (second person of the Trinity) is born in how we think of one being born. He also at times is quoting the arguments from the Arians so if you are not careful you may think he is agreeing with their heresy. So just read carefully these sections & you will see the strength & beauty of his reasoning & arguments.

It is a good read, take your time & allow yourself to digest what is said.
April 1,2025
... Show More
Clássico é clássico. Até pensei em tirar uma estrela pelas infinitas especulações em busca de uma imagem da trindade no homem, mas é mais provável que foi meu balde que não pôde conter o oceano agostiniano...
April 1,2025
... Show More
Many of the great Fathers of the Church wrote works on the Trinity. St. Augustine's work is perhaps the most well known of these. But unlike some of the other Patristic works on the Trinity, this one is not entirely an apologetic work against sects such as the Arians or the Macedonians who denied some aspect of the Trinity. The first part of the work is deeply apologetic, but later in the work St. Augustine gets far more philosophical about the nature of the Trinity and how, not just God, but human nature and even Creation takes on the Trinitarian nature of its creator.

Why would Christians believe this incredible doctrine that God is One but yet He is three persons? One can argue that the doctrine appears in scripture even as the word Trinity never appears there, and this is certainly true. One can also believe that various aspects of Christian belief would be incomprehensible if one did not believe in the Trinity. But the idea that a three-fold reality permeates more than just the divine nature. It is included in the created world as well.

I would highly recommend this work for anyone who wants to get a deeper understanding of the Trinity, not just the defense of the doctrine of the Trinity, but why is it important to believe in the Trinity.
April 1,2025
... Show More
I had read Augustine's City Of God a few years ago and I was impressed with it, although I didn't agree with all of Augustine's points. When I do agree, it is a rather strong agreement. The Trinity (aka De Trinitate) was similar in that when I do agree with Augustine, it is a strong agreement; where I disagreed, it was more a matter of not going with the extremes of his position. For instance, while Augustine is trying to give honor to all three members of the Trinity, his trinitarian theology does suffer from some inconsistencies; or at least some nagging remaining questions that are not properly addressed. He believes that the Son is indeed called God's Wisdom in scripture, but he also maintains that all members of the Trinity are wise because of the shared substance. He holds this position with all of the divine attributes. The most nagging question is whether this substance is to be identified with the Holy Spirit, and if it is, how He can be called the Substance while the Father and Son are not. If the substance is one of the other members, the same question remains. If the substance is different than all three, than Augustine is really introducing a fourth hypostasis and thus abrogating the Trinity. My feeling is that his weakness is an overly zealous method of dividing the Trinity in order to honor each member separately. I think he is looking at Them as if They were numerically separate, rather than numerically One and parabolically Three. At least that is the way I see it.
As it stands, I like his approach to the Old Testament. His assertion that the Old Testament did not reveal the Son in the same way the New Testament did I am in complete agreement with. Many of the earlier Fathers believed that the instances of the angel of the Lord in the OT were all of the Son in visible manifestation. I have had issues with that view. So did Augustine and he shows the problems with it and duly rejects that interpretation. The other thing I really liked in this book was Augustine's approach to salvation and the devil's role in humanity's bondage. There are some things in this approach that are too often missed nowadays in theology.
Overall a good read. I probably won't be reading any more of Augustine in the near future. The book was dragging by the end, but I was glad to have finally finished it. He's a noteworthy Church Father and well worth getting acquainted with. His influence on subsequent theology cannot be undervalued. Without Augustine, I am not sure if there would have been an Aquinas, Luther or Calvin.
April 1,2025
... Show More
I've been working on going through all of the relevant church writings regarding the Trinity. Hilary was an obvious resource. I am currently reading Augustine's work on the Trinity as well. I was never really in doubt that my understanding of the Trinity was orthodox, but I still wanted to know how the Fathers explained it. Their views are well worth reading. The doctrine of the Trinity goes back to the earliest traditions in the church. It did get modified as time went on though. Many of the Antenicene Fathers held to an unequal economic Trinity; meaning, the Son was less than the Father and the Holy Spirit was less than the Son. I thought this could be correct, until I read Gregory of Nyssa; after that, I was convinced of the rightness of the co-equal Trinity. The doctrine of the co-equal Trinity has been the orthodox view since the time of the Nicene Fathers. I do agree that it is the correct view.
April 1,2025
... Show More
Augustine's work on the Trinity truly illustrates the definition of the work "classic": a book much discussed but never read, either by his adherents or critics. To be fair, even Augustine's adherents admit his style could be improved--shortening passages and limiting some of the more fanciful exegesis (City of God is notorious in this regard). And as some of his critics point out, if you want a good introduction into Trinitarian thinking, Gregory of Nazianzus (or Basil) is clearer and is writing more within the mainstream of Nicene thought (yes, I am aware of Lewis Ayres' thesis, and I still maintain that last sentence).

On the other hand, a handful of books clearly define the thinking and development of Western civilization, and Augustine is responsible for at least three of them: City of God, Confessions, and De Trinitate.


In book II Augustine is dealing with the theophanies and how God revealed himself to the Fathers in the Old Testament. His larger argument is that the Trinity works in sending. The act of sending is a Trinitarian act.

Augustine rightly says that God's nature is invisible to human eyes. God's nature is not corporeal and cannot be seen by man. That is another way of saying the essentially correct thesis that God's essence cannot be comprehended by man. Because of that, Augustine reasons that the appearances (theophanies) in the Old Testament were essentially the ancient equivalent of holograms. Speaking of the Holy Spirit Augustine writes,

For in due time a certain outward appearance of the creature was wrought, wherein the Holy Spirit might be visibly shown (II. 5).

Now, instead of "Holy Spirit" one can also insert (as he does elsewhere) "Son" or "Father." While I am going to disagree with his above conclusion, his reasoning is consistent and bears some reflection. Augustine rightly notes that the Holy Spirit is "invisible." Obviously, the Father is invisible, also. After the incarnation, though, Jesus is not invisible. Augustine does not want to say that Jesus assumed flesh before the incarnation, and I think rightly so, so he opts for the temporary "creature" mode (e.g., Jesus assumes a temporary creature to show himself, not that Jesus is one).

Therefore, the only way the invisible God can manifest himself without committing to multiple incarnations is to assume some form of a temporary creature in the theophany. Augustine repeatedly uses the word "creature" and this can throw the reader off. With all due respect, however, I think the term "hologram" best describes what he is getting at.

Augustine is insistent that God's "nature" cannot be shown. Man's eye cannot see God's nature. That's why, I think, he insists that God appears to man via hologramic images. Augustine seems to reduce the argument to two options: either we see God's nature (which is impossible) or we see God by "the corporeal creature made subject to him, and not by his own substance" (II. 14).

Augustine then engages in an extended discourse on whether the theophanies were revelations of the entire Trinity or of one person. Personally, I don't know and I don't think Augustine does, either. He seems to entertain several positions. It is imperative to say that the Old Testament is a revelation of God the Son, but it is not entirely certain from that whether all theophanies were of the Son or of the Trinity. I don't see any reason to come to a hard conclusion on this.

Augustine ends this section with a helpful summary of Book II: which persons of the Trinity appeared to man, and their appearance via created means (II. 35).

Analysis

Must we accept Augustine's conclusion that the theophanies were holograms? He is correct that God's nature qua nature cannot be seen by corporeal eye. On the other hand, though, the Eastern fathers do have the concept of the divine energies which solves this problem. Augustine gives a meditation of Moses on Mt. Sinai and seeing the "back parts of God." Augustine maintains his thesis that man cannot see God. However, Moses does see God's glory. Now, is God's glory truly divine? Is it truly the presence of God? I don't see how any can deny this. Consider: it is God's presence to us, yet it is not simply his essence. It is God, yet it is clearly seen by human eyes (Lev. 9:6; Num. 20:6; Ex. 34:29-35).

This is why the category of the divine energies is so helpful. They are not merely God's "essence," but they are truly God and manifest God to us. This is the category Augustine needed.

De Trinitate, books 3-4
Book 3 is an extension upon several themes highlighted in Book 2: God's invisibility and incorporeality and how man saw revelations from God in the Old Testament. Augustine specifically deals with Angels and Miracles, and much of it is quite helpful. He wants to know "whether the angels were then the agents both in showing those bodily appearances to the eyes of men, and in sounding those words in their ears, when the sensible creature itself, serving the Creator at His beck, turned for the time into whatever was needful" (III.1.6).

It is helpful to keep in mind when Augustine says "creature" in this context he means the vehicle in which the divine appeared to the human. I said in the last review it was a type of hologram, but I think it is a little stronger than that. Presumably on Augustine's gloss, it is corporeal. Forgive the horrible cultural reference, but remember what was going on the movie Avatar. (!!).

Augustine makes his conclusion when he says "that all those appearances to the Fathers (old testament saints)...were wrought through the creature" (III.2.22). He then discuses when the Angel of the Lord appeared to Moses, whether it was an angel or God himself who actually appeared. Given his above conclusion Augustine maintains that it is an Angel who actually appears. Augustine actually does a good job in examining the difficulties in both positions, but one would have hoped he would have been consistent with his earlier theme and simply not come to a dogmatic conclusion on an issue that Scripture really doesn't say too much about. (He does note that St Stephen says in Acts 7 that the *angel* appeared to Moses).

The problem here is that Patristic exegesis reads the Old Testament as a Revelation of God the Son, not as a revelation of "an angel." While I understand what he is getting at, I have trouble affirming a conclusion--based on a dearth of evidence--which would lead me to contradict a key point of Patristic exegesis.

(In a rather humorous, if somewhat bitter, moment he goes back to Stephen's conclusion to the Sanhedrin and applies these words to whoever disagrees with him, "Ye stiff-necked..." cf. III.2.26).

Augustine then goes to say that man cannot see God's glory with his own eyes (III.2.24). Contrast this with Leviticus 9:5 and Numbers 20.6 where it says men will see God's glory. The problem here is that Augustine lacks the concept of the divine energies, so he is left with man either seeing God's essence (which is impossible) or only seeing a created intermediary. In either case, man never actually communes with God.

Book IV

Book IV is a wonderful meditation on Christ's reversal of the work of the devil. He discusses how the person of Christ takes our death into his death and resurrects us. One is struck by how Eastern and Patristic this sounds, and this should remind the reader that for all of Augustine's innovations and erroneous conclusions, he is still a faithful son of the Church. When he sticks to received Catholic doctrine that is common to the fathers, he is a wonderful guide to piety.


De Trinitate, books 5-6
Augustine is here responding to the Arian heretics who say that the nature of the Son is different from the nature of the Father. He modifies somewhat the traditional dictum that what is said of each person in respect to themselves is to be taken in the singular (V.8.9). (Or something like that. Augustine's argumentation here is very convoluted and is open to many interpretations. He also appears in this section to anticipate the "relations of opposition" canard popular in the later middle ages. I will interpret him for now as holding to the classical triadic dictum: what is said of all three persons is said of the essence, and what is unique to one person is unique to that person). It should be noted, however, that Augustine is not always using the term "God" as the New Testament and early fathers used it: the God and Father of our Lord Jesus Christ. I am simply noting that for now, for it may become important later).

In chapter 10 of Book V Augustine advances and early form of the "Absolute Divine Simplicity" thesis, stating "that it is the same thing to God to be , and to be great (or wise, or love, etc)" (V.10.11). One way to interpret this line is that the term "Greatness" equally applies to all three persons, therefore it is common to the essence. On the other hand, it is not hard to see how this line of reasoning could equate God's attribute--greatness--with God's essence. And the obvious conclusion: if God's attribute a = God's essence, and God's essence is absolutely simple, and God's attribute b (or x, y, and z) = God's essence, then attribute a = attribute b.

At this point in the narrative Augustine doesn't say any more, so I will leave it at that. In the next chapter (11), Augustine says that since the Father is Holy, and the Son is Holy, and the Holy Spirit is holy by definition, then the entire Trinity can be said to be the Holy Spirit (V.11.12)! This leads Augustine to his famous line that the Holy Spirit is the communion of Father and Son.

What just happened here?
Keep in mind what was said earlier: what is common to all is common to the essence; what is unique of one is unique to that one person. It appears that the Holy Spirit is both common to the essence and unique to a person. It also looks like the Holy Spirit has become an attribute of God. I am sure there are more able interpretations in defense of Blessed Augustine, but it looks like this is a confusion of both person and nature.

In chapter 13 Augustine anticipates later Filioquist discussions. Given his commitment to the unity of the Trinity, he wants to say that all persons share in the principium (or the beginning), and from this he denies there are two Beginnings. He writes,

"But if whatever remains within itself and produces or works anything is a beginning to that thing which it produces or works; then we cannot deny that the Holy Spirit also is rightly called Beginning, since we do not separate him from the appellation of Creator" (V.13.14).

In other words, only the Creator (or non-creatures) can participate in the principium. It seems then that active participation in the Principium is common to the essence, since it is common to all (V.13.14). However, in the next section he says that the Father and Son are the principium of the Holy Spirit. He ends his discussion on principium noting, "But the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit is one Beginning in respect to the creature, as also one Creator and one God."

In other words, the Holy Spirit does not participate in the Principium in the same way that the Father and Son participate. While Augustine formally avoids calling the Holy Spirit a creature by noting he, too, is principium, at the same time it appears that the Holy Spirit does not participate with the Father and Son. This strains the Triadic logic mentioned above and has the practical effect of subordinating the Holy Spirit.

Book VI

Augustine wrestles with some of his implications in the previous book. If Christ is the Wisdom and Power of God the Father, and obviously assuming "wisdom" and "power" common to the essence, one must wonder if the Father is not wise apart from Christ. Granted this is an abstraction, since one cannot speak of the Persons apart from one another, but it is an important question. If one answers in the affirmative, Augustine notes, one must conclude that the Father is not wise in himself (VI.1.2). I refer the reader to Peter Leithart's post on this topic, "Conundrums of Simplicity."


De Trinitate, books 7-8
In book seven Augustine continues his discussion of the problem whether the Father is wise in himself or wise only when speaking the Word, who is Wisdom. He is taking his cue from St Paul, who says that Christ is the Wisdom and Power of God. While much of Augustine's discussion is laborious and belabors the point, it is a fair question. St Athanasius wrestled with the same question, though his answer was more straightfoward (if not entirely avoiding the problem. Instead of "Wisdom," Athanasios was discussing whether Christ was willed by the Father. He denied the Arian dilemma by saying that Christ was the willing of the Father).

Notwithstanding the similarities of the problem, Augustine has to fight it on a different front. Throughout the treatise he has affirmed that God is identical with his attributes (this is more clearly stated in City of God bk. 11, c. 10). If it is true, Augustine reasons, that in the Father it is not one thing to be, and another to be wise, but to be is to be wise. And if Christ is the wisdom of God, how is Christ not also the essence of God? Further, if the Father is "wise in himself," and yet the Son also is Wisdom, are they not of different essences? This is the heart of the problem.

Augustine answers it by saying what is said of the persons is said relatively. He writes, "but the Son is begotten: since by these names only their relative attributes are expressed. But both together are one essence and one wisdom; in which to be, is the same as to be wise...as we have already sufficiently shown that these terms [Word, Son] are spoken relatively" (VII.2.3).

Augustine goes on to discuss the differences between Greek and Latin triadologies, and his discussion is limited by his lack of knowledge of Greek. He is identifying the terms (not the concepts) "person" and "substance." This was a legitimate way to speak of it in parts of the Roman Empire; it seems, however, that Augustine is reading his own understanding of "substance" back into Greek, which was quite different. And from that reading he appears to draw a number of conclusions:
it is the same thing with God to be (esse) as to subsist (subsistere).
Therefore, he subsists relatively, as he begets relatively, as he bears rule relatively (VII.4.9).

One tentative conclusion he does not necessarily draw here, but will be made with great force by Thomas Aquinas, is that the persons are identical in essence by different only relatively, in terms of relation. While it is true the persons share and fully possess an identical essence, it seems dangerous to say that the persons are identical. On the other hand, this appears to be the logical conclusion of absolute divine simplicity. Latin scholastics would avoid the trap only by saying there are "notional distinctions in God." But are notional distinctions real distinctions? If they are, then how do you maintain ADS? If they aren't, then does it even matter to call them notional distinctions?

For further discussion the reader is urged to consider J. N. D. Kelly's Early Christian Doctrines, pp. 271-279.

Book VIII

Augustine ends his exegetical discussion of the Trinity for now and begins his famous psychological analysis. He has been criticized for saying there are psychological analogies to the Trinity, and perhaps positing some sort of analogia entis. Maybe so. I don't think analogies are helpful, nor I suspect do most people think them helpful, either. However, it is an interesting discussion and as they say more about human loving and the mind, I think it can be read with profit.

Actually, there is a very good discussion of the nature of speech (VIII.6.9). I think his point in this book is that any of these (lover, object loved, and the love that unites them) cannot ideally be separated (again, see Kelly, 277).

If we want to use these analogies to properly understand the Trinity, I think it dead-ends, and badly so. However, if, like St Maximos the Confessor, we want to say that man is a triadic being, and reality itself is triadic (see Maximos: Genesis, Kinesis, Stasis), then Augustine's exposition is quite helpful.

Book XV

Book XV is the most important of the sections.   Books 9-14 can easily be skipped for the analogies.   As a wee child in Sunday School I was rightly taught that the Trinity is 3 Persons/1 essence.   I was also taught that analogies of the Trinity fail miserably.    Augustine spent 100 pages defending and explaining trinitarian analogies.    I am not going to "critique" the analogies, since I can't imagine any but  few would take them seriously.

In any case, Book XV neatly summarizes the entire work and ends with some of Augustine's stronger conclusions.   The main point is Augustine sets forth what will later harden as "double procession."   I still don't see it as a hard Filioquist reading, since the latin word procedere is ambiguous, but it certainly points that way.  For those who reference the Nicene and Post Nicene Fathers edition, on page 222 Augustine, in speaking of the divine nature, uses the phrase "equals."   Augustine's definition of simplicity, God is what he has, and that it is not one thing for God to be, and another to be wise, but to be is to be wise.   Combine that with the "equals" on page 222 (he is simply clarifying his point), then we are justified in positing that absolute divine simplicity is simply (no pun!) one big "=" sign.   Therefore, to be wise = just = love = wrath = God's essence.   

Unfortunately, St Paul said Christ is the wisdom of God, and I think Augustine sees the trap into which he walked.   Books 6 and 7 try to deal with this problem, and I think as long as Augustine holds to this form of simplicity, he can't avoid the conclusion that the Person of the Son is the essence of the Father (which we know is clearly wrong).

He ends the book discussing double procession.  His argument is fairly well-known and I won't belabor the point.   The Spirit proceeds from the Father principally  as from one clause.   So far, orthodox.   However, he also proceeds from the Son.   Chant "de Regnon" all you want, I don't care how you slice it--that is a real form of subordinationism.  The Spirit is now Jesus' lieutenant. 

Despite the painful meanderings from the point, the treatise is actually organized quite well.  With an exception of the last two books, each book can be read in about 10 minutes.
Leave a Review
You must be logged in to rate and post a review. Register an account to get started.